Before discussing the concept itself we must first consider the terms ideal and ideality, that is to say, we must first define the range of phenomena to which these terms may be applied, without analysing the essence of these phenomena at this point.
Even this is not an easy task because usage in general, and scientific usage in particular, is always something derivative of that very understanding of the essence of the question whose exposition our definition is intended to serve. The difficulty is by no means peculiar to the given case. It arises whenever we discuss fairly complex matters regarding which there is no generally accepted interpretation and, consequently, no clear definition of the limits of the object under discussion. In such cases discussion on the point at issue turns into an argument about the meaning of the term, the limits of a particular designation and, hence, about the formal attributes of phenomena that have to be taken into consideration in a theoretical examination of the essence of the question.
Returning to the subject of the ideal, it must be acknowledged that the word ideal is used today mainly as a synonym for conceivable, as the name for phenomena that are immanent in the consciousness, phenomena that are represented, imagined or thought. If we accept this fairly stable connotation, it follows that there is no point in talking about any ideality of phenomena existing outside human consciousness. Given this definition, everything that exists outside the consciousness and is perceived as existing outside it is a material and only a material object.
At first sight this use of the term seems to be the only reasonable one. But this is only at first sight.
Of course, it would be absurd and quite inadmissible from the standpoint of any type of materialism to talk about anything ideal where no thinking individual (thinking in the sense of mental or brain activity) is involved. Ideality is a category inseparably linked with the notion that human culture, human life activity is purposeful and, therefore, includes the activity of the human brain, consciousness and will. This is axiomatic and Marx, when contrasting his position regarding the ideal to Hegels view, writes that the ideal is nothing else than the material world reflected by the human mind, and translated into forms of thought. [Capital, Vol. I, Moscow, 1974, p. 29]
It does not follow from this, however, that in the language of modern materialism the term ideal equals existing in the consciousness, that it is the name reserved for phenomena located in the head, in the brain tissue, where, according to the ideas of modern science, consciousness is realised.
In Capital Marx defines the form of value in general as purely ideal not on the grounds that it exists only in the consciousness, only in the head of the commodity-owner, but on quite opposite grounds. The price or the money form of value, like any form of value in general, is IDEAL because it is totally distinct from the palpable, corporeal form of commodity in which it is presented, we read in the chapter on Money. [Capital, Vol. I, pp. 98-99.]
In other words, the form of value is IDEAL, although it exists outside human consciousness and independently of it.
This use of the term may perplex the reader who is accustomed to the terminology of popular essays on materialism and the relationship of the material to the ideal. The ideal that exists outside peoples heads and consciousness, as something completely objective, a reality of a special kind that is independent of their consciousness and will, invisible, impalpable and sensuously imperceptible, may seem to them something that is only imagined, something suprasensuous.
The more sophisticated reader may, perhaps, suspect Marx of an unnecessary flirtation with Hegelian terminology, with the semantic tradition associated with the names of Plato, Schelling and Hegel, typical representatives of objective idealism, i.e., of a conception according to which the ideal exists as a special world of incorporeal entities (ideas) that is outside and independent of man. He will be inclined to reproach Marx for an unjustified or incorrect use of the term ideal, of Hegelian hypostatisation of the phenomena of the consciousness and other mortal sins, quite unforgivable in a materialist.
But the question is not so simple as that. It is not a matter of terminology at all. But since terminology plays a most important role in science, Marx uses the term ideal in a sense that is close to the Hegelian interpretation just because it contains far more meaning than does the popular pseudo-materialistic understanding of the ideal as a phenomenon of consciousness, as a purely mental function. The point is that intelligent (dialectical) idealism the idealism of Plato and Hegel is far nearer the truth than popular materialism of the superficial and vulgar type (what Lenin called silly materialism). In the Hegelian system, even though in inverted form, the fact of the dialectical transformation of the ideal into the material and vice versa was theoretically expressed, a fact that was never suspected by silly materialism, which had got stuck on the crude undialectical opposition of things outside the consciousness to things inside the consciousness, of the material to the ideal.
The popular understanding of the ideal cannot imagine what insidious traps the dialectics of these categories has laid for it in the given case.
Marx, on the other hand, who had been through the testing school of Hegelian dialectics, discerned this flaw of the popular materialists. His materialism had been enriched by all the achievements of philosophical thought from Kant to Hegel. This explains the fact that in the Hegelian notion of the ideal structure of the universe existing outside the human head and outside the consciousness, he was able to see not simply idealistic nonsense, not simply a philosophical version of the religious fairy-tales about God (and this is all that vulgar materialism sees in the Hegelian conception), but an idealistically inverted description of the actual relationship of the mind to Nature, of the ideal to the material, of thought to being. This also found its expression in terminology.
We must, therefore, briefly consider the history of the term ideal in the development of German classical philosophy from Kant to Hegel, and the moral that the intelligent (i.e., dialectical) materialist Marx was able to draw from this history.
It all began when the founder of German classical philosophy, Immanuel Kant, took as his point of departure the popular interpretation of the concepts of the ideal and the real without suspecting what pitfalls he had thus prepared for himself.
It is notable that in his Critique of Pure Reason Kant does not formulate his understanding of ideality, but uses this term as a ready-made predicate requiring no special explanation when he is defining space and time and speaking of their transcendental ideality. This means that things possess space-time determinacy only in the consciousness and thanks to the consciousness, but not in themselves, outside and before their appearance in the consciousness. Here ideality is clearly understood as a synonym for the pure and the a priori nature of consciousness as such, with no external connections. Kant attaches no other meaning to the term ideality.
On the other hand, the material element of cognition is achieved by sensations, which assure us of the existence (and only that!) of things outside consciousness. Thus, all we know about things in themselves is that they exist. The ideal is what exists exclusively in the consciousness and thanks to the activity of the consciousness. And conversely, that which exists only in consciousness is characterised as the ideal. All clear and simple. A perfectly popular distinction. And what it amounts to is that none of the facts we know and are aware of in things their colour, geometrical form, taste, causal interdependence may be attributed to the things themselves. All these are merely attributes provided by our own organisation, and not those of the things. In other words, the ideal is everything that we know about the world except the bare fact of its existence, its being outside consciousness. The latter is non-ideal and, therefore, inaccessible to consciousness and knowledge, transcendental, alien, and awareness of the fact that things, apart from anything else, also exist (outside the consciousness) adds nothing whatever to our knowledge of them. And it is this interpretation that Kant illustrates with his famous example of the talers. It is one thing, he writes, to have a hundred talers in ones pocket, and quite another thing to have them only in ones consciousness, only in imagination, only in dreams (i.e., from the standpoint of popular usage, only ideal talers).
In Kants philosophy this example plays an extremely important role as one of the arguments against the so-called ontological proof of the existence of God. His argument runs as follows. It cannot be inferred from the existence of an object in the consciousness that the object exists outside the consciousness. God exists in peoples consciousness but it does not follow from this that God exists in fact, outside consciousness. After all, there are all kinds of things in peoples consciousness! Centaurs, witches, ghosts, dragons with seven heads....
With this example, however, Kant gets himself into a very difficult position. In fact, in a neighbouring country where the currency was not talers but rubles or francs it would have been simply explained to him that he had in his pocket not real talers but only pieces of paper with symbols carrying an obligation only for Prussian subjects.... However, if one acknowledges as real only what is authorised by the decrees of the Prussian king and affirmed by his signature and seal, Kants example proves what Kant wanted it to prove. If, on the other hand, one has a somewhat wider notion of the real and the ideal, his example proves just the opposite. Far from refuting, it actually affirms that very ontological proof which Kant declared to be a typical example of the erroneous inferring of the existence of a prototype outside the consciousness from the existence of the type in the consciousness.
The contrary is true. Kants example might have enforced the ontological proof, wrote Marx, who held a far more radical atheistic position than Kant in relation to God. And he went on: Real talers have the same existence that the imagined gods have. Has a real taler any existence except in the imagination, if only in the general or rather common imagination of man? Bring paper money into a country where this use of paper is unknown, and everyone will laugh at your subjective imagination. [Karl Marx, Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 1, Moscow, 1975, p. 104]
The reproach aimed at Kant does not, of course, derive from a desire to change the meaning of the terms ideal and real after the Hegelian fashion. Marx bases his argument on realisation of the fact that a philosophical system which denotes as real everything that man perceives as a thing existing outside his own consciousness, and ideal everything that is not perceived in the form of such a thing, cannot draw critical distinctions between the most fundamental illusions and errors of the human race.
It is quite true that the real talers are in no way different from the gods of the primitive religions, from the crude fetishes of the savage who worships (precisely as his god!) an absolutely real and actual piece of stone, a bronze idol or any other similar external object. The savage does not by any means regard the object of his worship as a symbol of God; for him this object in all its crude sensuously perceptible corporeality is God, God himself, and no mere representation of him.
The very essence of fetishism is that it attributes to the object in its immediately perceptible form properties that in fact do not belong to it and have nothing in common with its sensuously perceptible external appearance.
When such an object (stone or bronze idol, etc.) ceases to be regarded as God himself and acquires the meaning of an external symbol of this God, when it is perceived not as the immediate subject of the action ascribed to it, but merely as a symbol of something else outwardly in no way resembling the symbol, then mans consciousness takes a step forward on the path to understanding the essence of things.
For this reason Kant himself and Hegel, who is completely in agreement with him on this point, consider the Protestant version of Christianity to be a higher stage in the development of the religious consciousness than the archaic Catholicism, which had, indeed, not progressed very far from the primitive fetishism of the idol-worshippers. The very thing that distinguishes the Catholic from the Protestant is that the Catholic tends to take everything depicted in religious paintings and Bible stories literally, as an exact representation of events that occurred in the external world (God as a benevolent old man with a beard and a shining halo round his head, the birth of Eve as the actual conversion of Adams rib into a human being, etc., etc.). The Protestant, on the other hand, seeing idolatry in this interpretation, regards such events as allegories that have an internal, purely ideal, moral meaning.
The Hegelians did, in fact, reproach Kant for playing into the hands of Catholic idolatry with his example of the talers, for arguing against his own Protestant sympathies and attitudes because the external talers (the talers in his pocket) were only symbols in the general or rather common imagination of man, were only representatives (forms of external expression, embodiment) of the spirit, just as religious paintings, despite their sensuously perceptible reality, were only images produced by human social self-consciousness, by the human spirit. In their essence they were entirely ideal, although in their existence they were substantial, material and were located, of course, outside the human head, outside the consciousness of the individual, outside individual mental activity with its transcendental mechanisms.
Gods and talers are phenomena of the same order, Hegel and the Hegelians declared, and by this comparison the problem of the ideal and its relationship to the real, to the materially substantial world was posited in a way quite different from that of Kant. It was associated with the problem of alienation, with the question of reification and de-reification, of mans re-assimilation of objects created by himself, objects that through the action of some mysterious processes had been transformed into a world not only of external objective formations but formations that were also hostile to man.
Hence comes the following interpretation of Kants problem: The proofs of the existence of God are either mere hollow tautologies. Take for instance the ontological proof. This only means: that which 1 conceive for myself in a real way (realiter) is a real concept for me, something that works on me. In this sense all gods, the pagan as well as the Christian ones, have possessed a real existence. Did not the ancient Moloch reign? Was not the Delphic Apollo a real power in the life of the Greeks? Kants critique means nothing in this respect. If somebody imagines that he has a hundred talers, if this concept is not for him an arbitrary, subjective one, if he believes in it, then these hundred imagined talers have for him the same value as a hundred real ones. For instance, he will incur debts on the strength of his imagination, his imagination will work, in the same way as all humanity has incurred debts on its gods. [Karl Marx, Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 1, Moscow, 1975, p. 104]
When the question was posited in this way the category of the ideal acquired quite a different meaning from that given to it by Kant, and this was by no means due to some terminological whim of Hegel and the Hegelians. It expressed the obvious fact that social consciousness is not simply the many times repeated individual consciousness (just as the social organism in general is not the many times repeated individual human organism), but is, in fact, a historically formed and historically developing system of objective notions, forms and patterns of the objective spirit, of the collective reason of mankind (or more directly, the people with its inimitable spiritual culture), all this being quite independent of individual caprices of consciousness or will. This system comprises all the general moral nor ms regulating peoples daily lives, the legal precepts, the forms of state political organisation of life, the ritually legitimised patterns of activity in all spheres, the rules of life that must be obeyed by all, the strict regulations of the guilds, and so on and so forth, up to and including the grammatical and syntactical structures of speech and language and the logical norms of reasoning.
All these structural forms and patterns of social consciousness unambiguously oppose the individual consciousness and will as a special, internally organised reality, as the completely external forms determining that consciousness and will. It is a fact that every individual must from childhood reckon far more carefully with demands and restrictions than with the immediately perceptible appearance of external things and situations or the organic attractions, desires and needs of his individual body.
It is equally obvious that all these externally imposed patterns and forms cannot be identified in the individual consciousness as innate patterns. They are all assimilated in the course of upbringing and education that is, in the course of the individuals assimilation of the intellectual culture that is available and that took shape before him, without him and independently of him as the patterns and forms of that culture. These are no immanent forms of individual mental activity. They are the forms of the other, external subject that it assimilates.
This is why Hegel sees the main advantage of Platos teaching in the fact that the question of the relationship of spirit to nature is for the first time posited not on the narrow basis of the relations of the individual soul to everything else, but on the basis of an investigation of the universal (social-collective) world of ideas as opposed to the world of things. In Platos doctrine ...the reality of the spirit, insofar as it is opposed to nature, is presented in its highest truth, presented as the organisation of a state. [G.W.F. Hegel, Sämtliche Werke, Bd. 18, Stuttgart, 1928, S. 269.]
Here it must be observed that by the term state Plato understood not only the political and legal superstructure, but also the sum-total of social rules regulating the life of individuals within an organised society, the polis, or any similar formation, everything that is now implied by the broader term culture.
It is from Plato, therefore, that the tradition arises of examining the world of ideas (he, in fact, gives us the concept of the ideal world) as a stable and internally organised world of laws, rules and patterns controlling the individuals mental activity, the individual soul, as a special, supernatural objective reality standing in opposition to every individual and imperatively dictating to the individual how he should act in any given situation. The immediate external force determining the conduct of the individual is the state, which protects the whole system of spiritual culture, the whole system of rights and obligations of every citizen.
Here, in a semi-mystical, semi-mythological form was clearly established a perfectly real fact, the fact of the dependence of the mental (and not only mental) activity of the individual on the system of culture established before him and completely independently of him, a system in which the spiritual life of every individual begins and runs its course.
The question of the relationship of the ideal to the substantially material was here presented as a question of the relationship of these stable forms (patterns, stereotypes) of culture to the world of individual things, which included not only external things, but also the physical body of man himself.
As a matter of fact, it was only here that the necessity arose for a clear definition of the category of ideality as opposed to the undifferentiated, vague notion of the psyche in general, which might equally well be interpreted as a wholly corporeal function of the physically interpreted soul, no matter to what organ this function was actually ascribed heart, liver or brain. Otherwise, ideality remains a superfluous and completely unnecessary verbal label for the psychic. This is what it was before Plato, the term idea being used, even by Democritus, to designate a completely substantial form, the geometrical outlines of a thing, a body, which was quite physically impressed on man, in the physical body of his eyes. This usage which was characteristic of the early, naive form of materialism cannot, of course, be used by the materialism of today, which takes into consideration all the complexity of the relationships between individual mental activity and the world of things.
For this reason in the vocabulary of modern materialistic psychology (and not only philosophy) the category of ideality or the ideal defines not mental activity in general, but only a certain phenomenon connected, of course, with mental activity, but by no means merging with it.
Ideality mainly characterises the idea or image insofar as they, becoming objectivised in words [entering into the system of socially evolved knowledge which for the individual is something that is given for him. E. I.], in objective reality, thus acquire a relative independence, separating themselves, as it were, from the mental activity of the individual, writes the Soviet psychologist S. L. Rubinstein. [Bytie i soznanie (Being and Consciousness), Moscow, 1957, p. 41]
Only in this interpretation does the category of ideality become a specifically meaningful definition of a certain category of phenomena, establishing the form of the process of reflection of objective reality in mental activity, which is social and human in its origin and essence, in the social-human consciousness, and ceases to be an unnecessary synonym for mental activity in general.
With reference to the quotation from S. L. Rubinsteins book it need only be observed that the image is objectivised not only in words, and may enter into the system of socially evolved knowledge not only in its verbal expression. The image is objectivised just as well (and even more directly) in sculptural, graphic and plastic forms and in the form of the routine-ritual ways of dealing with things and people, so that it is expressed not only in words, in speech and language, but also in drawings, models and such symbolic objects as coats of arms, banners, dress, utensils, or as money, including gold coins and paper money, IOUs, bonds or credit notes.
Ideality in general is in the historically formed language of philosophy a characteristic of the materially established (objectivised, materialised, reified) images of human social culture, that is, the historically formed modes of human social life, which confront the individual possessing consciousness and will as a special supernatural objective reality, as a special object comparable with material reality and situated on one and the same spatial plane (and hence often identified with it).
For this reason, purely for the sake of terminological accuracy, it is pointless to apply this definition to purely individual mental states at any given moment. The latter, with all their individually unique whims and variations, are determined in effect by the numerous interconnections of the most diverse factors up to and including transient states of the organism and the peculiar features of its biochemical reactions (such as allergy or colour-blindness, for instance), and, therefore, may be considered on the plane of social-human culture as purely accidental.
This is why we find Kant talking about the ideality of space and time, but not about the ideality of the conscious sensations of weight, for instance, in the muscles of the arm when one is carrying something; about the ideality of the chain of cause and effect, but not about the ideality of the fact that a rock with the sun shining on it becomes warmer (although this fact is also consciously perceived). In Kant ideality becomes a synonym for the transcendental character of universal forms of sensuousness and reason, that is, patterns of cognitive activity that are inherent in every self and thus have a completely impersonal character and display, moreover, a compulsive force in relation to each separate (empirical) self. This is why space and time, causal dependence and beauty are for Kant ideal, while they are not mental states connected with the unique and transitory physical states of the individuals body. Admittedly, as we have seen in the example of the talers, Kant does not always adhere strictly to his terminology, although the reason for this is certainly not carelessness (it would be difficult to reproach Kant for that), but rather the dialectical trickiness of the problems that he raises. But despite the instability of the terminological definition of the categories, their objective dialectical content begins to show through the very content that the Hegelian school provides with a far more adequate definition. The point is that Kant could not fully overcome the notion of social consciousness (universal spirit) as the many times repeated individual consciousness.
In Hegelian philosophy, however, the problem was stated in a fundamentally different way. The social organism (the culture of the given people) is by no means an abstraction expressing the sameness that may be discovered in the mentality of every individual, an abstract inherent in each individual, the transcendentally psychological pattern of individual life activity. The historically built up and developing forms of the universal spirit (the spirit of the people, the objective spirit), although still understood by Hegel as certain stable patterns within whose framework the mental activity of every individual proceeds, are none the less regarded by him not as formal abstractions, not as abstractly universal attributes inherent in every individual, taken separately. Hegel (following Rousseau with his distinction between the general will and the universal will) fully takes into account the obvious fact that in the diverse collisions of differently orientated individual wills certain results are born and crystallised which were never contained in any of them separately, and that because of this social consciousness as an entity is certainly not built up, as of bricks, from the sameness to be found in each of its parts (individual selves, individual consciousnesses). And this is where we are shown the path to an understanding of the fact that all the patterns which Kant defined as transcendentally inborn forms of operation of the individual mentality, as a priori internal mechanisms inherent in every mentality, are actually forms of the self-consciousness of social man assimilated from without by the individual (originally they opposed him as external patterns of the movement of culture independent of his will and consciousness), social man being understood as the historically developing aggregate of all social relations.
It is these forms of the organisation of social (collectively realised) human life activity that exist before, outside and completely independently of the individual mentality, in one way or another materially established in language, in ritually legitimised customs and rights and, further, as the organisation of a state with all its material attributes and organs for the protection of the traditional forms of life that stand in opposition to the individual (the physical body of the individual with his brain, liver, heart, hands and other organs) as an entity organised in itself and for itself, as something ideal within which all individual things acquire a different meaning and play a different role from that which they had played as themselves, that is, outside this entity. For this reason the ideal definition of any thing, or the definition of any thing as a disappearing moment in the movement of the ideal world, coincides in Hegel with the role and meaning of this thing in social human culture, in the context of socially organised human life activity, and not in the individual consciousness, which is here regarded as something derived from the universal spirit.
It will readily be appreciated how much broader and more profound such a positing of the question is in comparison with any conception that designates as ideal everything that is in the consciousness of the individual, and material or real, everything that is outside the consciousness of the individual, everything that the given individual is not conscious of, although this everything does exist in reality, and thus draws between the ideal and the real a fundamentally dividing line which turns them into different worlds that have nothing in common with each other. It is clear that, given such a metaphysical division and delimitation, the ideal and the material cannot and must not be regarded as opposites. Here they are different, and that is all.
Hegel proceeds from the quite obvious fact that for the consciousness of the individual the real and even the crudely material certainly not the ideal is at first the whole grandiose materially established spiritual culture of the human race, within which and by the assimilation of which this individual awakens to self-consciousness. It is this that confronts the individual as the thought of preceding generations realised (reified, objectified, alienated) in sensuously perceptible matter in language and visually perceptible images, in books and statues, in wood and bronze, in the form of places of worship and instruments of labour, in the designs of machines and state buildings, in the patterns of scientific and moral systems, and so on. All these objects are in their existence, in their present being substantial, material, but in their essence, in their origin they are ideal, because they embody the collective thinking of people, the universal spirit of mankind.
In other words, Hegel includes in the concept of the ideal everything that another representative of idealism in philosophy (admittedly he never acknowledged himself to be an idealist)A. A. Bogdanov a century later designated as socially organised experience with its stable, historically crystallised patterns, standards, stereotypes, and algorithms. The feature which both Hegel and Bogdanov have in common (as idealists) is the notion that this world of socially organised experience is for the individual the sole ,,object which he assimilates and cognises, the sole object with which he has any dealings.
But the world existing before, outside and independently of the consciousness and will in general (i.e., not only of the consciousness and will of the individual but also of the social consciousness and the socially organised will), the world as such, is taken into account by this conception only insofar as it finds expression in universal forms of consciousness and will, insofar as it is already idealised, already assimilated in experience, already presented in the patterns and forms of this experience, already included therein.
By this twist of thought, which characterises idealism in general (whether it is Platonic, Berkeleian, Hegelian or that of Popper), the real material world, existing before, outside and quite independently of experience and before being expressed in the forms of this experience (including language), is totally removed from the field of vision, and what begins to figure under the designation of the real world is an already idealised world, a world already assimilated by people, a world already shaped by their activity, the world as people know it, as it is presented in the existing forms of their culture. A world already expressed (presented) in the forms of the existing human experience. And this world is declared to be the only world about which anything at all can be said.
This secret of idealism shows up transparently in Hegels discussion of the ideality of natural phenomena, in his presentation of nature as an ideal being in itself. Underlying what he has to say about certain natural phenomena is their description in the concepts and terms of the physics of his day: ...because masses push and crush each other and there is no vacuum between them, it is only in this contact that the ideality of matter in general begins, and it is interesting to see how this intrinsic character of matter emerges, for in general it is always interesting to see the realisation of a concept. [G.W.F. Hegel, Sämtliche Werke, Bd. 9, Stuttgart, 1929, S. 101.] Here Hegel is really speaking not at all about nature as it is, but about nature as it is presented (described) in the system of a definite physical theory, in the system of its definitions established by its historically formed language.
It is this fact, incidentally, that explains the persistent survival of such semantic substitutions; indeed, when we are talking about nature, we are obliged to make use of the available language of natural science, the language of science with its established and generally understood meanings. It is this, specifically, which forms the basis of the arguments of logical positivism, which quite consciously identifies nature with the language in which people talk and write about nature.
It will be appreciated that the main difficulty and, therefore, the main problem of philosophy is not to distinguish and counterpose everything that is in the consciousness of the individual to everything that is outside this individual consciousness (this is hardly ever difficult to do), but to delimit the world of collectively acknowledged notions, that is, the whole socially organised world of intellectual culture with all its stable and materially established universal patterns, and the real world as it exists outside and apart from its expression in these socially legitimised forms of experience.
It is here and only here that the distinction between the ideal and the real (material) acquires a serious scientific meaning because in practice the two are usually confused. Pointing out the fact that the thing and the form of the thing exist outside the individual consciousness and do not depend on individual will still does not solve the problem of their objectivity in its fully materialistic sense. And conversely, by no means all that people do not know, are unaware of, do not perceive as the forms of external things, is invention, the play of the imagination, a notion that exists merely in mans head. It is because of this that the sensible person, to whose way of thinking Kant appeals with his example of the talers, is more often than other people deluded into taking the collectively acknowledged notions for objective reality, and the objective reality revealed by scientific research for subjective invention existing only in the heads of the theoreticians. It is the sensible person, daily observing the sun rising in the East and setting in the West, who protests that the system of Copernicus is an invention that contradicts the obvious facts. And in exactly the same way the ordinary person, drawn into the orbit of commodity-money relationships, regards money as a perfectly material thing, and value, which in fact finds its external expression in money, as a mere abstraction existing only in the heads of the theoreticians, only ideally.
For this reason consistent materialism, faced with this kind of situation, could not define the ideal as that which exists in the consciousness of the individual, and the material as that which exists outside this consciousness, as the sensuously perceived form of the external thing, as a real corporeal form. The boundary between the two, between the material and the ideal, between the thing in itself and its representation in social consciousness could not pass along this line because, if it did, materialism would be completely helpless when confronted with the dialectics that Hegel had discovered in the relations between the material and the ideal (particularly, in the phenomena of fetishism of all kinds, from that of religion to that of commodity, and further, the fetishism of words, of language, symbols and signs).
It is a fact that like the icon or the gold coin, any word (term or combination of terms) is primarily a thing that exists outside the consciousness of the individual, possesses perfectly real bodily properties and is sensuously perceived. According to the old classification accepted by everyone, including Kant, words clearly come under the category of the material with just as much justification as stones or flowers, bread or a bottle of wine, the guillotine or the printing press. Surely then, in contrast to these things, what we call the ideal is their subjective image in the head of the individual, in the individual consciousness.
But here we are immediately confronted with the trickiness of this distinction, which is fully provided for by the Hegelian school and its conception of the materialisation, the alienation, the reification of universal notions. As a result of this process which takes place behind the back of the individual consciousness, the individual is confronted in the form of an external thing with peoples general (i.e., collectively acknowledged) representation, which has absolutely nothing in common with the sensuously perceived bodily form in which it is represented.
For example, the name Peter is in its sensuously perceived bodily form absolutely unlike the real Peter, the person it designates, or the sensuously represented image of Peter which other people have of him. The relationship is the same between the gold coin and the goods that can be bought with it, goods (commodities), whose universal representative is the coin or (later) the banknote. The coin represents not itself but another in the very sense in which a diplomat represents not his own person but his country, which has authorised him to do so. The same may be said of the word, the verbal symbol or sign, or any combination of such signs and the syntactical pattern of this combination.
This relationship of representation is a relationship in which one sensuously perceived thing performs the role or function of representative of quite another thing, and, to be even more precise, the universal nature of that other thing, that is, something other which in sensuous, bodily terms is quite unlike it, and it was this relationship that in the Hegelian terminological tradition acquired the title of ideality.
In Capital Marx quite consciously uses the term ideal in this formal meaning that it was given by Hegel, and not in the sense in which it was used by the whole pre-Hegelian tradition, including Kant, although the philosophical-theoretical interpretation of the range of phenomena which in both cases is similarly designated ideal is diametrically opposed to its Hegelian interpretation. The meaning of the term ideal in Marx and Hegel is the same, but the concepts, i.e., the ways of understanding this same meaning are profoundly different. After all, the word concept in dialectically interpreted logic is a synonym for understanding of the essence of the matter, the essence of phenomena which are only outlined by a given term; it is by no means a synonym for the meaning of the term, which may be formally interpreted as the sum-total of attributes of the phenomena to which the term is applied.
It was for this reason that Marx, like any genuine theoretician, preferred not to change the historically formed meanings of terms, the established nomenclature of phenomena, but, while making strict and rigorous use of it, proposed a quite different understanding of these phenomena that was actually the opposite of the traditional understanding.
In Capital, when analysing money that familiar and yet mysterious category of social phenomena Marx describes as ideal nothing more or less than the value-form of the products of labour in general (die Wertform �berhaupt).
So the reader for whom the term ideal is a synonym for the immanent in the consciousness, existing only in the consciousness, only in peoples ideas, only in their imagination will misunderstand the idea expressed by Marx because in this case it turns out that even Capital which is nothing else but a value-form of the organisation of the productive forces, a form of the functioning of the means of production also exists only in the consciousness, only in peoples subjective imagination, and not in reality.
Obviously only a follower of Berkeley could take the point in this way, and certainly not a materialist.
According to Marx, the ideality of the form of value consists not, of course, in the fact that this form represents a mental phenomenon existing only in the brain of the commodity-owner or theoretician, but in the fact that the corporeal palpable form of the thing (for example, a coat) is only a form of expression of quite a different thing (linen, as a value) with which it has nothing in common. The value of the linen is represented, expressed, embodied in the form of a coat, and the form of the coat is the ideal or represented form of the value of the linen.
As a use-value, the linen is something palpably different from the coat; as value, it is the same as the coat, and now has the appearance of a coat. Thus the linen acquires a value-form different from its physical form. The fact that it is value, is made manifest by its equality with the coat, just as the sheeps nature of a Christian is shown in his resemblance to the Lamb of God. [Capital, Vol. I, p. 58.]
This is a completely objective relationship, within which the bodily form of commodity B becomes the value-form of commodity A, or the body of commodity B acts as a mirror to the value of commodity A, [Capital, Vol. I, p. 59.] the authorised representative of its value nature, of the substance which is embodied both here and there.
This is why the form of value or value-form is ideal, that is to say, it is something quite different from the palpable form of the thing in which it is represented, expressed, embodied, alienated.
What is this other, this difference, which is expressed or represented here? Peoples consciousness? Their will? By no means. On the contrary, both will and consciousness are determined by this objective ideal form, and the thing that it expresses, represents is a definite social relationship between people which in their eyes assumes the fantastic form of a relationship between things.
In other words, what is represented here as a thing is the form of peoples activity, the form of life activity which they perform together, which has taken shape behind the back of consciousness and is materially established in the form of the relationship between things described above.
This and only this creates the ideality of such a thing, its sensuous-supersensuous character.
Here ideal form actually does stand in opposition to individual consciousness and individual will as the form of the external thing (remember Kants talers) and is necessarily perceived precisely as the form of the external thing, not its palpable form, but as the form of another equally palpable thing that it represents, expresses, embodies, differing, however, from the palpable corporeality of both things and having nothing in common with their sensuously perceptible physical nature. What is embodied and represented here is a definite form of labour, a definite form of human objective activity, that is to say, the transformation of nature by social man.
It is here that we find the answer to the riddle of ideality. Ideality, according to Marx, is nothing else but the form of social human activity represented in the thing. Or, conversely, the form of human activity represented as a thing, as an object.
Ideality is a kind of stamp impressed on the substance of nature by social human life activity, a form of the functioning of the physical thing in the process of this activity. So all the things involved in the social process acquire a new form of existence that is not included in their physical nature and differs from it completely their ideal form.
So, there can be no talk of ideality where there are no people socially producing and reproducing their material life, that is to say, individuals working collectively and, therefore, necessarily possessing consciousness and will. But this does not mean that the ideality of things is a product of their conscious will, that it is immanent in the consciousness and exists only in the consciousness. Quite the reverse, the individuals consciousness and will are functions of the ideality of things, their comprehended, conscious ideality.
Ideality, thus, has a purely social nature and origin. It is the form of a thing, but it is outside this thing, and in the activity of man, as a form of this activity. Or conversely, it is the form of a persons activity but outside this person, as a form of the thing. Here, then, is the key to the whole mystery that has provided a real basis for all kinds of idealistic constructions and conceptions both of man and of a world beyond man, from Plato to Carnap and Popper. Ideality constantly escapes, slips away from the metaphysically single-valued theoretical fixation. As soon as it is fixed as the form of the thing it begins to tease the theoretician with its immateriality, its functional character and appears only as a form of pure activity. On the other hand, as soon as one attempts to fix it as such, as purified of all the traces of palpable corporeality, it turns out that this attempt is fundamentally doomed to failure, that after such a purification there will be nothing but phantasmal emptiness, an indefinable vacuum.
And indeed, as Hegel understood so well, it is absurd to speak of ,activity that is not realised in anything definite, is not embodied in something corporeal, if only in words, speech, language. If such ,activity exists, it cannot be in reality but only in possibility, only potentially, and, therefore, not as activity but as its opposite, as inactivity, as the absence of activity.
So, according to Hegel, the spirit, as something ideal, as something opposed to the world of corporeally established forms, cannot reflect at all (i.e., become aware of the forms of its own structure) unless it preliminarily opposes itself to itself, as an object, a thing that differs from itself.
When speaking of value-form as the ideal form of a thing, Marx by no means accidentally uses the comparison of the mirror: In a sort of way, it is with man as with commodities. Since he comes into the world neither with a looking glass in his hand, nor as a Fichtean philosopher, to whom I am I is sufficient, man first sees and recognises himself in other men. Peter only establishes his own identity as a man by first comparing himself with Paul as being of like kind. And thereby Paul, just as he stands in his Pauline personality, becomes to Peter the type of the genus homo. [Capital, Vol. I, p. 59.]
Here Marx plainly indicates the parallel between his theory of the ideality of the value-form and Hegels understanding of ideality, which takes into account the dialectics of the emergence of the collective self-awareness of the human race. Yes, Hegel understood the situation far more broadly and profoundly than the Fichtean philosopher; he established the fact that spirit, before it could examine itself, must shed its unblemished purity and phantasmal nature, and must itself turn into an object and in the form of this object oppose itself to itself. At first in the form of the Word, in the form of verbal embodiment, and then in the form of instruments of labour, statues, machines, guns, churches, factories, constitutions and states, in the form of the grandiose inorganic body of man, in the form of the sensuously perceptible body of civilisation which for him serves only as a glass in which he can examine himself, his other being, and know through this examination his own pure ideality, understanding himself as pure activity. Hegel realised full well that ideality as pure activity is not directly given and cannot be given as such, immediately in all its purity and undisturbed perfection; it can be known only through analysis of its embodiments, through its reflection in the glass of palpable reality, in the glass of the system of things (their forms and relationships) created by the activity of pure spirit. By their fruits ye shall know them-and not otherwise.
The ideal forms of the world are, according to Hegel, forms of activity realised in some material. If they are not realised in some palpable material, they remain invisible and unknown for the active spirit itself, the spirit cannot become aware of them. In order to examine them they must be reified, that is, turned into the forms and relations of things. Only in this case does ideality exist, does it possess present being; only as a reified and reifiable form of activity, a form of activity that has become and is becoming the form of an object, a palpable thing outside consciousness, and in no case as a transcendental-psychological pattern of consciousness, not as the internal pattern of the self, distinguishing itself from itself within itself, as it turned out with the Fichtean philosopher.
As the internal pattern of the activity of consciousness, as a pattern immanent in the consciousness, ideality can have only an illusory, only a phantasmal existence. It becomes real only in the course of its reification, objectification (and deobjectification), alienation and the sublation of alienation. How much more reasonable and realistic this interpretation was, compared with that of Kant and Fichte, is self-evident. It embraced the actual dialectics of peoples developing self-consciousness, it embraced the actual phases and metamorphoses in whose succession alone the ideality of the world exists.
It is for this reason that Marx joins Hegel in respect of terminology, and not Kant or Fichte, who tried to solve the problem of ideality (i.e., activity) while remaining inside consciousness, without venturing into the external sensuously perceptible corporeal world, the world of the palpable forms and relations of things.
This Hegelian definition of the term ideality took in the whole range of phenomena within which the ideal, understood as the corporeally embodied form of the activity of social man, really exists.
Without an understanding of this circumstance it would be totally impossible to fathom the miracles performed before mans eyes by the COMMODITY, the commodity form of the product, particularly in its money form, in the form of the notorious real talers, real rubles, or real dollars, things which, as soon as we have the slightest theoretical understanding of them, immediately turn out to be not real at all, but ideal through and through, things whose category quite unambiguously includes words, the units of language, and many other things. Things which, while being wholly material, palpable formations, acquire all their meaning (function and role) from spirit and even owe to it their specific bodily existence .... Outside spirit and without it there cannot even be words, there is merely a vibration of the air.
The mysteriousness of this category of things, the secret of their ideality, their sensuous-supersensuous character was first revealed by Marx in the course of his analysis of the commodity (value) form of the product.
Marx characterises the commodity form as an IDEAL form, i.e., as a form that has absolutely nothing in common with the real palpable form of the body in which it is represented (i.e., expressed, materialised, reified, alienated, realised), and by means of which it exists, possesses present being.
It is ideal because it does not include a single atom of the substance of the body in which it is represented, because it is the form of quite another body. And this other body is present here not bodily, materially (bodily it is at quite a different point in space), but only once again ideally, and here there is not a single atom of its substance. Chemical analysis of a gold coin will not reveal a single molecule of boot-polish, and vice versa. Nevertheless, a gold coin represents (expresses) the value of a hundred tins of boot-polish precisely by its weight and gleam. And, of course, this act of representation is performed not in the consciousness of the seller of boot-polish, but outside his consciousness in any sense of this word, outside his head, in the space of the market, and without his having even the slightest suspicion of the mysterious nature of the money form and the essence of the price of boot-polish.... Everyone can spend money without knowing what money is.
For this very reason the person who confidently uses his native language to express the most subtle and complex circumstances of life finds himself in a very difficult position if he takes it into his head to acquire consciousness of the relationship between the sign and the meaning. The consciousness which he may derive from linguistic studies in the present state of the science of linguistics is more likely to place him in the position of the centipede who was unwise enough to ask himself which foot he steps off on. And the whole difficulty which has caused so much bother to philosophy as well lies in the fact that ideal forms, like the value-form, the form of thought or syntactical form, have always arisen, taken shape and developed, turned into something objective, completely independent of anyones consciousness, in the course of processes that occur not at all in the head, but most definitely outside it although not without its participation.
If things were different, the idealism of Plato and Hegel would, indeed, be a most strange aberration, quite unworthy of minds of such calibre and such influence. The objectivity of the ideal form is no fantasy of Platos or Hegels, but an indisputable and stubborn fact. A fact that such impressive thinkers as Aristotle, Descartes, Spinoza, Kant, Hegel and Einstein, not to mention thousands of lesser spirits, racked their brains over throughout the centuries.
Idealism is not a consequence of some elementary mistake committed by a naive schoolboy who saw a terrible ghost that was not there. Idealism is a completely sober statement of the objectivity of ideal form, that is, the fact of its existence in the space of human culture independently of the will and consciousness of individuals a statement that was, however, left without an adequate scientific explanation.
This statement of the fact without its scientific materialist explanation is what idealism is. In the given case materialism consists precisely in the scientific explanation of this fact and not in ignoring it. Formally this fact looks just as it was described by the thinkers of the Platonic line a form of movement of physically palpable bodies which is objective despite its obvious incorporeality. An incorporeal form controlling the fate of entirely corporeal forms, determining whether they are to be, or not to be, a form, like some fleshless, and yet all-powerful soul of things. A form that preserves itself in the most diverse corporeal embodiments and does not coincide with a single one of them. A form of which it cannot be said WHERE EXACTLY it exists.
A completely rational, non-mystical understanding of the ideal (as the ideal form of the real, substantially material world) was evolved in general form by Marx in the course of his constructive critical mastering of the Hegelian conception of ideality, and particularised (as the solution to the question of the form of value) through his criticism of political economy, that is to say, of the classical labour theory of value. The ideality of value-form is a typical and characteristic case of ideality in general, and Marxs conception of it serves as a concrete illustration of all the advantages of the dialectical materialist view of ideality, of the ideal.
Value-form is understood in Capital precisely as the reified form (represented as, or representing, the thing, the relationship of things) of social human life activity. Directly it does present itself to us as the physically palpable embodiment of something other, but this other cannot be some physically palpable matter.
The only alternative, it appears, is to assume some kind of bodiless substance, some kind of insubstantial substance. And classical philosophy here proposed a logical enough solution: such a strange substance can be only activity pure activity, pure form-creating activity. But in the sphere of economic activity this substance was, naturally, decoded as labour, as mans physical labour transforming the physical body of nature, while value became realised labour, the embodied act of labour.
So it was precisely in political economy that scientific thought made its first decisive step towards discovering the essence of ideality. Already Smith and Ricardo, men fairly far removed from philosophy, clearly perceived the substance of the mysterious value definitions in labour.
Value, however, though understood from the standpoint of its substance, remained a mystery with regard to its form. The classical theory of value could not explain why this substance expressed itself as it did, and not in some other way. Incidentally, the classical bourgeois tradition was not particularly interested in this question. And Marx clearly demonstrated the reason for its indifference to the subject. At all events, deduction of the form of value from its substance remained an insuperable task for bourgeois science. The ideality of this form continued to be as mysterious and mystical as ever.
However, since the theoreticians found themselves in direct confrontation with the mysterious physically impalpable properties of this form, they had recourse again and again to the well-known ways of interpreting ideality. Hence, the idea of the existence of ideal atoms of value, which were highly reminiscent of Leibnizs monads, the immaterial and unextended quanta of spiritual substance.
Marx, as an economist, was helped by the fact that he knew a lot more about philosophy than Smith and Ricardo.
It was when he saw in the Fichtean-Hegelian conception of ideality as pure activity an abstractly mystifying description of the real, physically palpable labour of social man, the process of the physical transformation of physical nature performed by mans physical body, that he gained the theoretical key to the riddle of the ideality of value-form.
The value of a thing presented itself as the reified labour of man and, therefore, the form of value turned out to be nothing else but the reified form of this labour, a form of human life activity.
And the fact that this is by no means the form of the thing as it is (i.e., the thing in its natural determinateness) but a form of social human labour or of the form-creating activity of social man embodied in the substance of nature it was this fact that provided the solution to the riddle of ideality. The ideal form of a thing is not the form of the thing in itself, but a form of social human life activity regarded as the form of a thing.
And since in its developed stages human life activity always has a purposeful, i.e., consciously willed character, ideality presents itself as a form of consciousness and will, as the law guiding mans consciousness and will, as the objectively compulsory pattern of consciously willed activity. This is why it turns out to be so easy to portray the ideal exclusively as a form of consciousness and self-consciousness, exclusively as the transcendental pattern of the psyche and the will that realises this pattern.
And if this is so, the Platonic-Hegelian conception of ideality begins to appear as merely an impermissible projection of the forms of consciousness and will (forms of thought) on to the external world. And the criticism of Hegel amounts merely to reproaches for his having ontologised, hypostatised the purely subjective forms of human mental activity. This leads to the quite logical conclusion that all categories of thought (quantity, measure, necessity, essence, and so on and so forth) are only ideal, that is, only transcendental-psychological patterns of the subjects activity and nothing else.
Marx, of course, had quite a different conception. According to him all the logical categories without exception are only the idealised (i.e., converted into forms of human life activity, activity that is primarily external and sensuously objective, and then also spiritual), universal forms of existence of objective reality, of the external world. And, certainly, not projections of the forms of the mental world on to the physical world. A conception, as can easily be seen, which is just the reverse in the sequence of its theoretical deduction.
This interpretation of ideality is in Marx based, above all, on the materialist understanding of the specific nature of the social human relationship to the world (and the fundamental difference between this and the animals relationship to the world, the purely biological relationship): The animal is immediately one with its life activity. It does not distinguish itself from it. It is its life activity. Man makes his life activity itself the object of his will and of his consciousness. [Marx, Estranged Labour, 1844, in Karl Marx, Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 3, Moscow, 1975, p. 276]
This means that the animals activity is directed only towards external objects. The activity of man, on the other hand, is directed not only on them, but also on his own forms of life activity. It is activity directed upon itself, what German classical philosophy presented as the specific feature of the spirit, as reflection, as self-consciousness.
In the above passage quoted from Marxs early works he does not emphasise sufficiently the fundamentally important detail that distinguishes his position from the Fichtean-Hegelian interpretation of reflection (the relationship to oneself as to another). In view of this the passage may be understood to mean that man acquires a new, second plane of life activity precisely because he possesses consciousness and will, which the animal does not possess.
But this is just the opposite of the case. Consciousness and will appear in man only because he already possesses a special plane of life activity that is absent in the animal world activity directed towards the mastering of forms of life activity that are specifically social, purely social in origin and essence, and, therefore, not biologically encoded in him.
The animal that has just been born is confronted with the external world. The forms of its life activity are inborn along with the morphology of its body and it does not have to perform any special activity in order to master them. It needs only to exercise the forms of behaviour encoded in it. Development consists only in the development of instincts, congenital reactions to things and situations. The environment merely corrects this development.
Man is quite a different matter. The child that has just been born is confronted outside itself not only by the external world, but also by a very complex system of culture, which requires of him modes of behaviour for which there is genetically (morphologically) no code in his body. Here it is not a matter of adjusting ready-made patterns of behaviour, but of assimilating modes of life activity that do not bear any relationship at all to the biologically necessary forms of the reactions of his organism to things and situations.
This applies even to the behavioural acts directly connected with the satisfaction of biologically inborn needs: the need for food is biologically encoded in man, but the need to eat it with the help of a plate, knife, fork and spoon, sitting on a chair, at a table, etc., etc., is no more congenital in him than the syntactical forms of the language in which he learns to speak. In relation to the morphology of the human body these are as purely and externally conventional as the rules of chess.
These are pure forms of the external (existing outside the individual body) world, forms of the organisation of this world, which he has yet to convert into the forms of his individual life activity, into the patterns and modes of his activity, in order to become a man.
And it is this world of the forms of social human life activity that confronts the newborn child (to be more exact, the biological organism of the species Homo Sapiens) as the objectivity to which he is compelled to adapt all his behaviour, all the functions of his organic body, as the object towards assimilation of which his elders guide all his activity.
The existence of this specifically human object the world of things created by man for man, and, therefore, things whose forms are reified forms of human activity (labour), and certainly not the forms naturally inherent in them is the condition for the existence of consciousness and will And certainly not the reverse, it is not consciousness and will that are the condition and prerequisite for the existence of this unique object, let alone its cause.
The consciousness and will that arise in the mind of the human individual are the direct consequence of the fact that what he is confronted by as the object of his life activity is not nature as such, but nature that has been transformed by the labour of previous generations, shaped by human labour, nature in the forms of human life activity.
Consciousness and will become necessary forms of mental activity only where the individual is compelled to control his own organic body in answer not to the organic (natural) demands of this body but to demands presented from outside, by the rules accepted in the society in which he was born. It is only in these conditions that the individual is compelled to distinguish himself from his own organic body. These rules are not passed on to him by birth, through his genes, but are imposed upon him from outside, dictated by culture, and not by nature.
It is only here that there appears the relationship to oneself as to a single representative of another, a relationship unknown to the animals. The human individual is obliged to subordinate his own actions to certain rules and patterns which he has to assimilate as a special object in order to make them rules and patterns of the life activity of his own body.
At first they confront him as an external object, as the forms and relationships of things created and recreated by human labour. It is by mastering the objects of nature in the forms created and recreated by human labour that the individual becomes for the first time a man, becomes a representative of the human race, whereas before this he was merely a representative of a biological species.
The existence of this purely social legacy of forms of life activity, that is to say, a legacy of forms that are in no way transmitted through the genes, through the morphology of the organic body, but only through education, only through assimilation of the available culture, only through a process in the course of which the individuals organic body changes into a representative of the RACE (i.e., the whole specific aggregate of people connected by the ties of social relationships) it is only the existence of this specific relationship that brings about consciousness and will as specifically human forms of mental activity.
Consciousness only arises where the individual is compelled to look at himself as if from the side as if with the eyes of another person, the eyes of all other people only where he is compelled to correlate his individual actions with the actions of another man, that is to say, only within the framework of collectively performed life activity. Strictly speaking, it is only here that there is any need for WILL, in the sense of the ability to forcibly subordinate ones own inclinations and urges to a certain law, a certain demand dictated not by the individual organics of ones own body, but by the organisation of the collective body, the collective, that has formed around a certain common task.
It is here and only here that there arises the IDEAL plane of life activity unknown to the animal. Consciousness and will are not the cause of the manifestation of this new plane of relationships between the individual and the external world, but only the mental forms of its expression, in other words, its effect. And, moreover, not an accidental but a necessary form of its manifestation, its expression, its realisation.
We shall go no further in examining consciousness and will (and their relationship to ideality) because here we begin to enter the special field of psychology. But the problem of ideality in its general form is equally significant for psychology, linguistics, and any socio-historical discipline, and naturally goes beyond the bounds of psychology as such and must be regarded independently of purely psychological (or purely politico-economic) details.
Psychology must necessarily proceed from the fact that between the individual consciousness and objective reality there exists the mediating link of the historically formed culture, which acts as the prerequisite and condition of individual mental activity. This comprises the economic and legal forms of human relationships, the forms of everyday life and forms of language, and so on. For the individuals mental activity (consciousness and will of the individual) this culture appears immediately as a system of meanings, which have been reified and confront him quite objectively as non-psychological, extra-psychological reality. [This question is examined in greater detail in A. N. Leontyevs article Activity and Consciousness included in this volume.]
Hence interpretation of the problem of ideality in its purely psychological aspect does not bring us much nearer to a correct understanding of it because the secret of ideality is then sought not where it actually arises: not in space, where the history of the real relationships between social man and nature is enacted, but in the human head, in the material relationships between nerve endings. And this is just as absurd an undertaking as the idea of discovering the form of value by chemical analysis of the gold or banknotes in which this form presents itself to the eye and sense of touch.
The riddle and solution to the problem of idealism is to be found in the peculiar features of mental activity of the subject, who cannot distinguish between two fundamentally different and even opposed categories of phenomena of which he is sensuously aware as existing outside his brain: the natural properties of things, on the one hand, and those of their properties which they owe not to nature but to the social human labour embodied in these things, on the other.
This is the point where such opposites as crudely naive materialism and no less crudely naive idealism directly merge. That is to say, where the material is directly identified with the ideal and vice versa, where all that exists outside the head, outside mental activity, is regarded as material and everything that is in the head, in the consciousness; is described as ideal.
Real, scientific materialism lies not in declaring everything that is outside the brain of the individual to be primary, in describing this primary as material, and declaring all that is in the head to be secondary and ideal. Scientific materialism lies in the ability to distinguish the fundamental borderline in the composition of palpable, sensuously perceptible things and phenomena, to see the difference and opposition between the material and the ideal there and not somewhere else.
The ideal plane of reality comprises only that which is created by labour both in man himself and in the part of nature in which he lives and acts, that which daily and hourly, ever since man has existed, is produced and reproduced by his own social human and, therefore, purposeful transforming activity.
So one cannot speak of the existence of an ideal plane in the animal (or in an uncivilised, purely biologically developed man) without departing from the strictly established philosophical meaning of the term.
Man acquires the ideal plane of life activity only through mastering the historically developed forms of social activity, only together with the social plane of existence, only together with culture. Ideality is nothing but an aspect of culture, one of its dimensions, determining factors, properties. In relation to mental activity it is just as much an objective component as mountains and trees, the moon and the firmament, as the processes of metabolism in the individuals organic body. This is why people often confuse the ideal with the material, taking the one for the other. This is why idealism is not the fruit of some misapprehension, but the legitimate and natural fruit of a world where things acquire human properties while people are reduced to the level of a material force, where things are endowed with spirit, while human beings are utterly deprived of it. The objective reality of ideal forms is no mere invention of the idealists, as it seems to the pseudo-materialists who recognise, on one side, the external world and on the other, only the conscious brain (or consciousness as a property and function of the brain). This pseudo-materialism, despite all its good intentions, has both feet firmly planted in the same mystical swamp of fetishism as its opponent principled idealism. This is also fetishism, only not that of the bronze idol or the Logos, but a fetishism of a nervous tissue, a fetishism of neurons, axons and DNAS, which in fact possess as little of the ideal as any pebble lying on the road. Just as little as the value of the diamond that has not yet been discovered, no matter how huge and heavy it might be.
Ideality is, indeed, necessarily connected with consciousness and will, but not at all in the way that the old, pre-Marxist materialism describes this connection. It is not ideality that is an aspect, or form of manifestation of the conscious-will sphere but, on the contrary, the conscious-will character of the human mentality is a form of manifestation, an aspect or mental manifestation of the ideal (i.e., socio-historically generated) plane of relationships between man and nature.
Ideality is a characteristic of things, not as they are determined by nature but as they are determined by labour, the transforming and form-creating activity of social man, his purposeful, sensuously objective activity.
The ideal form is the form of a thing created by social human labour. Or, conversely, the form of labour realised in the substance of nature, embodied in it, alienated in it, realised in it and, therefore, presenting itself to man the creator as the form of a thing or a relationship between things in which man, his labour, has placed them.
In the process of labour man, while remaining a natural being, transforms both external things and (in doing so) his own natural body, shapes natural matter (including the matter of his own nervous system and the brain, which is its centre), converting it into a means and organ of his purposeful life activity. This is why he looks upon nature (matter) from the very first as material in which his aims are ,embodied, and as the means of their realisation. This is why he sees in nature primarily what is suitable for this role, what plays or may play the part of a means towards his ends, in other words, what he has already drawn into the process of his purposeful activity.
Thus at first he directs his gaze at the stars exclusively as a natural clock, calendar and compass, as instruments of his life activity. He observes their natural properties and regularities only insofar as they are properties and regularities of the material in which his activity is being performed, and with these natural features he must, therefore, reckon as a completely objective component of his activity which is in no way dependent on his will and consciousness.
But it is for this very reason that he takes the results of his transforming activity (the forms and relations of things given by himself) as the forms and relations of things as they are. This gives rise to fetishism of every kind and shade, one of the varieties of which was and still is philosophical idealism, the doctrine which regards the ideal forms of things (i.e., the forms of human activity embodied in things) as the eternal, primordial and absolute forms @f the universe, and takes into account all the rest only insofar as this all the rest, that is to say, all the actual diversity of the world has already been drawn into the process of labour, already been made the means, instrument and material of realisation of purposeful activity, already been refracted through the grandiose prism of ideal forms (forms of human activity), is already presented (represented) in these forms, already shaped by them.
For this reason the ideal exists only in man. Outside man and beyond him there can be nothing ideal. Man, however, is to be understood not as one individual with a brain, but as a real aggregate of real people collectively realising their specifically human life activity, as the aggregate of all social relations arising between people around one common task, around the process of the social production of their life. It is inside man thus understood that the ideal exists, because inside man thus understood are all the things that mediate the individuals that are socially producing their life: words, books, statues, churches, community centres, television towers, and (above all!) the instruments of labour, from the stone axe and the bone needle to the modern automated factory and the computer. It is in these things that the ideal exists as the subjective, purposeful form-creating life activity of social man, embodied in the material of nature.
The ideal form is a form of a thing, but a form that is outside the thing, and is to be found in man as a form of his dynamic life activity, as goals and needs. Or conversely, it is a form of mans life activity, but outside man, in the form of the thing he creates. Ideality as such exists only in the constant succession and replacement of these two forms of its external embodiment and does not coincide with either of them taken separately. It exists only through the unceasing process of the transformation of the form of activity into the form of a thing and back the form of a thing into the form of activity (of social man, of course).
Try to identify the ideal with any one of these two forms of its immediate existence and it no longer exists. All you have left is the substantial, entirely material body and its bodily functioning. The form of activity as such turns out to be bodily encoded in the nervous system, in intricate neuro-dynamic stereotypes and cerebral mechanisms by the pattern of the external action of the material human organism, of the individuals body. And you will discover nothing ideal in that body. The form of the thing created by man, taken out of the process of social life activity, out of the process of man-nature metabolism, also turns out to be simply the material form of the thing, the physical shape of an external body and nothing more. A word, taken out of the organism of human intercourse, turns out to be nothing more than an acoustic or optical phenomenon. In itself it is no more ideal than the human brain.
And only in the reciprocating movement of the two opposing metamorphoses forms of activity and forms of things in their dialectically contradictory mutual transformations DOES THE IDEAL EXIST.
Therefore, it was only DIALECTICAL materialism that was able to solve the problem of the ideality of things.
SOURCE: Ilyenkov, E. V. "The Concept of the Ideal," in Problems of Dialectical Materialism, translated by Robert Daglish (Progress Publishers, 1977), pp. 71-99.
"From the Marxist-Leninist Point of View" by E. V. Ilyenkov
"The Universal" by E. V. Ilyenkov
"Humanism and Science" by E. V. Ilyenkov
Lenin and the Hegelian Conception of Thinking
by Evald Ilyenkov
Markso
kaj la okcidenta mondo
de E. V. Iljenkov, trad. Yury Finkel
Galvano Della Volpe on E. V. Ilyenkov
Evald Ilyenkov's Philosophy Revisited
The Problem of the Ideal (Extracts) by David Dubrovsky
"On Trends in the Status of Dialectical Logic: A Brief Study of Lefebvre, Ilyenkov and Wald" by Claude M. J. Braun
Cultural Impasse & the Changing Forms of Ideality
Salvaging Soviet Philosophy (1)
Offsite:
The Problem of the Ideal by David Dubrovsky
"The Concept of the Ideal" by E. V.
Ilyenkov (this essay)
at Marxists
Internet Archive & leninist.biz
The Value of Knowledge: a Miniature Library of Philosophy
Home Page | Site
Map | What's New | Coming Attractions | Book
News
Bibliography | Mini-Bibliographies | Study
Guides | Special Sections
My Writings | Other Authors' Texts | Philosophical
Quotations
Blogs | Images
& Sounds | External Links
CONTACT Ralph Dumain
Uploaded 6 October 2001
Site ©1999-2021 Ralph Dumain